The Fraud Act 2006: Has It Had Any Impact?
The Fraud Act 2006, which represents the most radical
change in the law of criminal fraud since the Theft Act 1968, came
into force on January 15, 2007. We are now over a year into the new
law, which seems a reasonable juncture to pose the question: has it
had any impact?
INTRODUCTION
It may simply be too early to tell what impact, if any, the
Fraud Act 2006 has had; its provisions do not apply
retrospectively, which means that only conduct which has taken
place entirely since January 15, 2007 can be prosecuted under the
new provisions. If we factor in the length of time which
investigations and prosecutions typically take, it is obvious that
the first major trials are only likely to be before the courts in
the coming months. There is then a further delay, of course, until
any cases are heard in the appeal courts, meaning there is a
paucity of reported cases, as well as a significant delay in the
publication of any useful prosecution and conviction
statistics.
I would ask instead, what impact can the Act be expected to
make? What are the problems and what were the solutions, both in
theory and in practice, based on what little anecdotal evidence
there is? I will therefore consider:
problems with the "old" law;
whether the Act can solve these problems;
that case law under the Act which does already exist;
prosecutorial attitudes towards the Act;
defence perspectives on the Act; and finally
other recent measures which may have an impact on fraud.
THE OLD LAW
The problems with the old law have been rehearsed many times
before; the Fraud Act was the response to long and sustained
criticism from the judiciary, practitioners and academics.
The overriding criticism of the law as it then stood was that
there were too many specific fraud offences, defined with reference
to different types of consequences and it was not always easy to
identify which offence to charge, and often, even less easy to
secure a conviction. This in turn led prosecutors, wherever
possible, to a rely heavily upon the common law offence of
conspiracy to defraud.
The specific nature of the law invited technical arguments. The
prime example of the problem arose in 1996 when section 15 of the
Theft Act 1968 (obtaining property belonging to another by
deception) came under judicial scrutiny in the case of
Preddy [1996] AC 815. The case concerned good old
fashioned mortgage fraud in which the defendants had obtained
mortgages from lenders on the basis of false representations.
The Court of Appeal held that where D dishonestly, and by
deception, procured a transaction whereby V's bank account was
debited and consequently there was a credit to D's account, D
had not obtained property belonging to another by deception. The
debt owed by V's bank to V had been extinguished, and what D
obtained was a newly created debt owed by his bank to him, not
property belonging to another. One chose in action had been
extinguished and another created; although a chose in action is
capable of being appropriated by another, here there were two
separate legal rights, not a single piece of property. This is fine
from a jurisprudential point of view and very neat logical
thinking, but a disaster in Magistrates' and Crown Courts
throughout the country.
The introduction of the new section 15A to the Theft Act 1968 by
the Theft (Amendment) Act 1996 followed very swift consultation on
the issue. Fears ran out across the legal and banking worlds that
those "appropriating" bank balances were now immune from
prosecution since no offence in the criminal calendar was able to
tackle the behaviour. Section 15A, which created a new offence of
obtaining a money transfer by deception, was intended to close the
Preddy loophole, by removing the requirement to show that
property "belonging to another" was obtained, in that as
long as a balance was transferred as a result of the deception it
did not matter that it was not the same legal property that was
obtained.
However, even this solution demonstrated the very problem from
which our criminal law suffered, namely that piecemeal reform did
nothing to tackle its over-technical nature and instead exacerbated
the problem of too many, over-specific offences. For example, the
1968 Act had already been amended by the Theft Act 1978 which
created new offences of obtaining services by deception, evasion of
a liability by deception, and making off without payment. The Theft
Act 1968 had itself been an attempt to codify and simplify a
complex web of offences created by the Larceny Act 1916. It is
almost as if legislators have a long and distinguished history of
over-complication in this area.
There were also difficulties with charging attempts. D attempts
to get a bank cashier to hand over money from an account; the
cashier is suspicious and refuses: D does not during this stage of
the process stipulate how he would like the transaction effected.
Had the deception worked, and depending upon what D had intended to
go on to say, the cashier could have either given cash, a cheque or
transferred money between accounts. There was certainly an attempt,
but of which offence?
The same could be said for conspiracies, although there are the
authorities to the effect that an agreement to commit either one or
another crime, although unlikely, is possible: Hussain
All these were certainly issues, but the most acute problem
which the Fraud Act 2006 was intended to remedy was the focus on
the mind of the victim, rather than the mind of the offender. Under
the old law it was necessary to prove that the deception had acted
on the victim, for example that he/she would not have parted with
the goods but for the deception. This increasingly created
difficulties as technology developed and the use of credit cards
and payment through machines or over the internet became
prevalent.
If, for example, payment is made by credit card with the vendor
receiving payment immediately from the card issuer, it may be that
the vendor does not really care whether or not the purchaser had
authority to use the card and does not give the matter any thought.
Although the House of Lords held that it was possible to infer that
the merchant did not wish to be a party to a fraud on the card
issue, and therefore that the deception could be inferred
(Charles [1977] AC 177 and Lambie [1982] AC 449),
what would happen if the merchant gave evidence that he did not
care? This was a tactic defence practitioners often deployed
(myself included): cross examination of the victim to demonstrate
that they gave no thought what so ever to the question of
representations, express or implied, and therefore any
misrepresentation did not "operate" upon their mind and
hence the property was not obtained as a result of any
deception.
There was also the problem that a machine, such as a ticket
machine at a railway station, does not have a "mind",
cannot think and therefore cannot be deceived: Holmes v The
Governor of Brixton Prison and another [2004] EWHC 2020.
A further problem resulting from the focus on the mind of the
victim rather than the offender was that, although a failure to
disclose may be as harmful and culpable as making a representation,
it was difficult for prosecutors to successfully imply a
representation from silence. People in positions of trust do not
need to make false representations to get what they want. They can
simply misuse what they have been entrusted with. A well known
example is that of the manager of a pub who sold his own beer on
his employer's premises; he was not guilty of theft and was not
guilty of conspiracy to defraud, because he was acting alone:
AG's Ref (No 1 of 1985) [1986] QB 491. However, two
employees who sold their sandwiches in place of British Rail ones
were guilty of conspiracy to defraud, as they acted together:
Cooke [1986] AC 909. The law created an anomalous
situation in which an act was capable of prosecution when carried
out by more than one person, but not when carried out by someone
acting alone.
Other problems included the fact that fraud (in the lay sense)
is not always committed with an obvious view to gain. There was no
offence of obtaining services without a deception, so jumping over
a turnstile at a football match could not easily be charged. In
addition to offences involving an element of deception or
"fraud" in the everyday sense, the Fraud Act 2006 was
also designed to deal with other specific lacunae in the existing
law such as these. The offence of going equipped to steal only
applied if the person was found with the necessary equipment
outside their own home, meaning it was legal to have, for example,
skimming devices at home. Fraudulent trading needed a corporate
entity: there was a potential injustice where a fraudster sought to
give the appearance that he was trading through a company but did
not go through any of the formalities of acquiring one.
Having noted these elements of the Fraud Act 2006 I am afraid I
must pass over them when considering whether the Act as a whole has
had any impact of fraud and instead I will focus on fraud in the
more everyday sense.
PROBLEMS SOLVED?
The new Act, which arises out of the Law Commission Report of
2002, goes back to the pre-1968 idea that it is not what the result
of conduct is, or its effect on the victim, which is important, but
rather the intention of the fraudster and what he/she actually
did.
The Act repeals all the deception offences in the Theft Acts of
1968 and 1978 and replaces them with a single offence of fraud (s
1), with a maximum sentence of 10 years imprisonment, which can be
committed in three different ways by:
false representation (s 2);
failure to disclose information when there is a legal duty to
do so (s 3); or
abuse of position (s 4).
The idea of having one offence of fraud, which can be committed
in three ways, seeks to sweep away the technicalities which beset
the old law by capturing the base elements of fraud, but in a
manner which is...
To continue reading
Request your trial